How to Be Responsible for Something without Causing It*
نویسنده
چکیده
condition that is realizable by different combinations of individual omissions by voters. For instance, consider an election with 100 potential voters, in which Bad gets 30 votes, Good gets 20, and the rest are abstentions. Suppose that all of the abstainers are like Lazy: they would have voted for Good if they had voted, but they abstained. Thus, given how things turned out, Good would have won if 11 of the abstainers had voted. It seems, then, that we want to blame the abstainers for the outcome of the election (as well as the people that voted for Bad). If my arguments in this paper are sound, we should say that none of the individual abstentions was a cause of the outcome. However, we could still argue that the fact that Good didn’t get 11 more votes from the pool of abstainers was a cause of the outcome (since, had at least 11 of the abstainers voted, Good would have won). There are different ways that the votes by the abstainers could have gone so that Good got 11 more votes from the abstainers pool. But never mind. If, as I have argued, causation is the vehicle of transmission of responsibility, to the extent that we could make each abstainer responsible for the fact that Good didn’t get 11 more votes from the abstainers pool, we could make each abstainer responsible for the outcome of the election. On this view, if a citizen abstains and the outcome of the election is bad, he is responsible for the outcome, not because he causes it, but because he is responsible for something that causes it. If so, the view that causation is the vehicle of responsibility could help us solve the voting problem.
منابع مشابه
Language without communication intention
This paper argues that a language can exist and flourish in a community even if none of of the members of the community has any communication intentions; and that reference to the notion of communication intention can therefore be dispensed with in the core account of the nature oflinguistic meaning. Certainly one cannot elucidate the notion of linguistic meaning without reference to psychologi...
متن کاملHistory in a Crisis — Lessons for Covid-19
Writing in the heady days of new antibiotics and immunizations, esteemed microbiologists Macfarlane Burnet and David White predicted in 1972 that “the most likely forecast about the future of infectious diseases is that it will be very dull.” When asked to explain past events, historians are quick to assert the importance of context. If you want to understand how or why something happened, you ...
متن کاملتجمع اسباب در خسارات پزشکی
The case of multiple causes in damages is vague in Iranian legal system and it has even more ambiguity when it comes to medical harm. However, specific rules related to medical damages has been stated at article 495 and 496 of Islamic criminal law. Moreover, in case of absence of law or conflict of law, it can be refuted to reliable fiqh resources according to article 167 substantial law. Ther...
متن کاملP 98: Neuroinflammation and Nanomedicine,How about Cerebral Palsy
Cerebral palsy (CP) is the most common motor disability in children, usually occurring during fetal development; before, during, or shortly after birth, or during infancy. CP takes place in about 2.1 per 1,000 live births .There is no exact reason but birth injury or inflammation of the central nervous system, infections and hypoxia are related risk factors of this disease. Often, symptoms incl...
متن کاملOn the Social Construction of Overdiagnosis; Comment on “Medicalisation and Overdiagnosis: What Society Does to Medicine”
In an interesting article Wieteke van Dijk and colleagues argue that societal developments and values influence the practice of medicine, and thus can result in both medicalisation and overdiagnosis. They provide a convincing argument that overdiagnosis emerges in a social context and that it has socially constructed implications. However, they fail to show that overdiagnosis per se is socially...
متن کامل